Two Skeptical Arguments
Guest Contributor

15 March 2009

Posted by John Greco

我一直声称有一些非常有力的怀疑论(在节目和回应Ken之前的帖子)。我还一直声称,他们的力量的一个方面是,他们不依赖于为知识设定很高的标准。这里有两个这样的论点。

1. Hume’s argument.
第一个灵感来自大卫·休谟。该论证首先假设,我们对外部世界的信念至少有一部分是基于事物的出现方式。例如,我相信我现在坐在我的桌子前,至少部分是因为这是事物在我视觉上呈现的方式。但这并不是全部,他们继续说。我还必须假设,至少是含蓄地假设,事物出现的方式很好地反映了事物的真实状态。休谟认为,如果我不依赖于那个假设,那么事物以某种方式呈现在我面前的事实,就不会成为我认为它们是那种方式的理由。但是现在我该如何证明这个关于表象可靠性的假设呢?我怎么能知道事物出现的方式就是事物真实存在的方式呢?休谟认为,没有办法证明这种假设是正确的。例如,假设我依赖于表象,推理出,就我所知,事物在我面前出现的方式,似乎是事物本来面目的可靠指示。 This, of course, would be to argue in a circle, taking for granted the very thing at issue. Here is Hume’s argument put more formally.

(H)

1. All my beliefs about the external world depend for their evidence on both a) the way things appear to me, and b) an assumption that the way things appear to me is a reliable indication of the way things really are.
2. But the assumption in question can’t be justified.
Therefore,
3. All my beliefs about the external world depend for their evidence on an unjustifiable assumption. (1, 2)
4. Beliefs that depend for their evidence on an unjustifiable assumption do not count as knowledge.
Therefore,
5.我关于外部世界的信仰都不能算作知识。我对外部世界一无所知。(3,4)

Clearly, a linchpin of this argument is premise (2): that an assumption regarding the reliability of appearances cannot be justified. In support of premise (2), Hume considers various possibilities for justifying the assumption in question. One consideration that Hume emphasizes is that the assumption is itself a contingent claim about the external world. That is, the assumption claims that sensory appearances are, as a matter of contingent fact, related to the way things are in a particular way. This suggests that the assumption can be justified, if at all, only in the way that contingent claims about the external world are justified in general—i.e. by relying on the way things appear! But this, of course, would be to argue in a circle, taking for granted the very thing at issue. Here again is the reasoning in support of (2).

(H2)

1. All my beliefs about the external world depend for their evidence on both a) the way things appear to me, and b) an assumption that the way things appear to me is a reliable indication of the way things really are.
2. The assumption in question is itself a belief about the external world.
Therefore,
3. The assumption depends on itself for its evidence. (1, 2)
4. Beliefs that that depend on themselves for their evidence can’t be justified.
Therefore,
5.这个假设是不合理的。(3, 4)

一种自然的想法是,表象是现实的可靠向导的假设可以通过其他一些方式得到证明,也许是通过某种独立于表象的先验反思。但休谟认为这条推理路线是一条死胡同。这是因为所讨论的假设对事物的方式作出了偶然的断言——现象是否反映事物的真实面貌,这是偶然事实的问题,而不是必然的问题。但是这种事实是不能通过先验的反思来知道的。简而言之,先验反思给予我们必要真理的知识,而不是偶然真理的知识。

2. Descartes’s argument.
The second skeptical argument is inspired by Descartes’s Meditation One, and in particular by Barry Stroud’s reading of that meditation. To understand the argument, consider the claim that one sees a goldfinch in the garden, based on one’s observation that the bird is of a particular size and color, and with a tail of a particular shape. Suppose now that a friend challenges one’s claim to know, pointing out that woodpeckers also are of that size and color, and also have tails with that shape. As Stroud points out, this seems to be a legitimate challenge to one’s claim to know that the bird is a goldfinch. More generally, if one’s evidence for one’s belief that the bird is a goldfinch is consistent with the possibility that it is in fact a woodpecker, then one does not know on the basis of that evidence that it is a goldfinch. Based on this sort of reasoning, the skeptic proposes the following plausible principle:

1. A person knows that p on the basis of evidence E, only if E rules out alternative possibilities to p.

Further support for this sort of principle comes from reflection on scientific enquiry. Suppose that there are several competing hypotheses for explaining some phenomenon, and suppose that these various hypotheses are “live” in the sense that current evidence does not rule them out as possibilities. It would seem that one cannot know that one of the hypotheses is true until further evidence rules out the remaining ones. Again, principle (1) above looks plausible.
怀疑论论证的第二步是指出,有各种各样的可能性,它们与我们所声称的对外部世界的认识是不一致的。例如,有可能事情在我看来就像现在一样,但我实际上是躺在床上睡着了,而不是坐在我的桌子上醒着。在笛卡尔看来,事情可能就是这样发生的,但他实际上是一个邪恶的恶魔的受害者,一个脱离肉体的灵魂,只梦想着他住在一个物质世界里,现在正坐在火边。需要明确的是,怀疑论者并不认为这种替代可能性是正确的,甚至不认为它们有一定的可能性。关键是,它们只是可能性,因此如果我们的证据不能排除它们,就会削弱我们的知识。
怀疑论论证的第三步是宣称我们的证据实际上并没有排除这些可能性。这一主张的主旨大致是这样的:这些可能性与我们所拥有或可能掌握的所有证据是一致的。实际上,即使我们通常不会考虑这些可能性,但经过反思,我们也没有现成的证据来反对它们,并支持我们的偏好信念。
如果我们把这三种说法放在一起,我们就有了有力的怀疑论论据。这里有一个更正式的论点。

(D)

1. A person knows that p on the basis of evidence E, only if E rules out alternative possibilities to p. (Principle 1 from above.)
2. It is a possibility that I am not sitting at my desk awake, but merely dreaming that I am.
Therefore,
3. I know that I am sitting at my desk only if my evidence rules out the possibility that I am merely dreaming. (1, 2)
4. But my evidence does not rule out this possibility.
Therefore,
5.我不知道我正坐在书桌前。(3, 4)

And of course the skeptical argument is supposed to generalize. That is, it is supposed to apply to beliefs about the external world in general. We therefore have:

6. The same line of reasoning can be brought to bear against any belief about the external world.
Therefore,
7. No one knows anything about the external world. (5, 6)

One way to understand the notion of “ruling out” a possibility is as follows: A body of evidence E rules out a possibility q if and only if E supports not-q in a non-circular way. Here we can understand support as a semantic notion: Evidence E supports propositions p, in the relevant sense, just in case E entails p or E makes p probable. Putting these ideas together, we get the following interpretation of premise (4) of argument (D).

4a. My evidence for my belief that I am sitting at my desk neither entails nor makes probable (in a non-circular way) the proposition that I am not dreaming.

Why might one accept premise (4a)? One reason for accepting (4a) is the considerations put forward by Hume’s argument above. That is, one might think that my evidence for believing that I am sitting at my desk is the way things appear to me, together with my assumption that the way things appear to me is a reliable indication of the way things are. But as Hume’s reasoning shows, there is no non-circular way to justify the assumption in question, and therefore no good evidence for either that assumption or further beliefs that are based on it. In particular, my evidence cannot entail or even make probable (in a non-circular way) the proposition that I am not dreaming. Insofar as this is the reasoning behind (4a), argument (D) is parasitic on argument (H).
There is, however, another way to understand the notion of evidence ruling out alternative possibilities. On this understanding, a body of evidence E rules out alternative possibilities to p just in case E discriminates the state of affairs represented by p from alternative states of affairs. For example, hearing my wife coming in the door from work, my auditory experience rules out the possibility that it is my children coming home from school or a burglar coming in through a window. In effect, I have the capacity to “tell the difference,” so to speak, and this is what allows me to know that it is my wife who has just come in the house. On this understanding of “ruling out”, it does seem plausible that my evidence must rule out alternative possibilities in order to ground knowledge. For example, how could I know that my wife has just come home, on the basis of hearing her come through the door, if I could not discriminate that state of affairs from my daughter’s coming through the door? Moreover, premise (4) of argument (D) becomes plausible on this understanding of “ruling out.” We now have

4b. My evidence does not discriminate my sitting at my desk from my merely dreaming that I am sitting at my desk.

One might think that this claim is obviously right. To be clear-- I assume that the skeptical argument must be wrong somewhere. My point here is that it isn't obvious where, or that the argument is invoking some very high standard for knowledge.

Comments(24)


Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, March 25, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

优秀的剧情简介。I think I agree with Professor

优秀的剧情简介。我想我同意泰勒教授的观点,即怀疑论的挑战是无法解决的,所以我们的知识讨论就简化为讨论为我们现象世界量身定做的信念形成策略。
Hume probably gave the only answer to the skeptical challenge one could hope to give, namely, that at the end of the day we all (do and probably should) set aside the assumptive and discriminative problems you've limned and go about "knowing" things about our world (such as it seems to us), with more or less fitting results. I might be trapped in a dream or a simulation, but then if so my best hope for escape would seem to lie in rational belief formation. For what other strategy is there?

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, March 25, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

The two skeptical arguments above are interesting,

The two skeptical arguments above are interesting, but I think Ken
was asking a question in his previous posts that has not
yet been addressed: are there powerful arguments
against rational (or justified or warranted) belief?
For instance, can we modify the above two arguments to produce
compelling arguments that no one can have justified beliefs about
外部世界吗?
This had some plausibility:
H.4 Beliefs that depend for their evidence on an unjustifiable assumption do not count as knowledge.
but what about this?
H.4* Beliefs that depend for their evidence on an unjustifiable assumption do not count as justified.
A similar change for D is changing this
D.1 A person knows that p on the basis of evidence E, only if E rules out alternative possibilities to p.
to this:
D.1* A person is justified in believing that p on the basis of evidence E, only if E rules out alternative possibilities to p.
As far I can see, the reasons given in support of D.1 (on the second
解析:选d。我不确定H.4*。

Guest's picture

Guest

Monday, March 26, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

很好的帖子,帕特里克。I think here we need to make

很好的帖子,帕特里克。我认为这里我们需要区分认知论证和实践论证(这与Q的评论和Ken Taylor的帖子有关)。我认为有一种熟悉的感觉,如果行动a或信念B是我最好或唯一的选择,那么它实际上是理性的。但怀疑者并不是在挑战相信这些信念或按照这些信念行事的实际合理性。相反,他/她是在挑战这种信念的认识论地位,并声称它没有基于足够好的认识论(表明真理)理由。我现在的观点是这样的,支持H.4*:我可以看到,有时根据认知上不合理的假设来相信或行动实际上是理性的。但是,如果一个人在认知上的不合理假设的基础上,就能得到认知上的合理,这就不太可信了。如果可以的话,这应该是一个很大的惊喜。

MIke's picture

MIke

Monday, March 26, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

John, Doesn't the Humean argument depend on kn

John,
Doesn't the Humean argument depend on knowing a priori that, necessarily, it is possible that the way things appear are not the way they are? If that proposition is not necessary, then it is not knowable a priori (on Hume's view). But it certainly does not seem to express a 'relation of ideas'. On the other hand it is not a matter of fact, either.
But setting that aside, I guess I don't see why the epistemological standards are not high in this argument. To know, I'm required to rule out every deceptive/misleading alternative. That seems like a fairly high epistemic standard.

aaron's picture

aaron

Monday, March 26, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

The skeptical arguments are useless because they c

The skeptical arguments are useless because they cannot be met. A creative person can always come up with a reason why an answer isn't the only one - Hume's denial of reality could be the basis for refuting ANY question. There has to be context to the question, or it becomes meaningless.
Consider the desk argument. We assume the following:
1) dreaming is different from reality
2) I am an individual
3) when I use the word "sit", it means the same thing to me as it does to you
4) that I am not quantumly sitting at one desk, while standing in an alternate universe
Etc, etc. The skeptic can find an infinite number of reasons not to believe that a person sits at his desk. At its worst, this line of thinking becomes semantic, rather than philosophical.
The point of philosophy, I believe, is to ask questions that are in context, that have certain parameters that are mutually agreed upon. If two people cannot agree about the most basic of facts to begin a question, then the question loses all meaning.

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Mike, I don't think of the skeptical arguments

Mike,
I don't think of the skeptical arguments as making knowledge claims themselves. Rather, they take claims that look good to us and show us where they lead. So I am not sympathetic to replies of the form "The skeptical argument assumes we know . . ."
I think your comment about an implict high standard is right. Maybe it is wrong to say we have to rule out every alternative possibility in order to know. But now things get interesting. We would like a principled account of which possibilities need to be ruled out and which do not, and if we can give one I think we will learn something about the nature of knowledge in the process.
I have some ideas about what account to give here:
http://plato.stanford.edu/entries/epistemology-virtue/

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Aaron, I am not sure what your position is rega

Aaron,
我不确定你在这场争论中的立场。你说无法回答,但为什么?因为它不会出错?但是,我们缺乏知识的结论是正确的。如果你认为我们确实有知识(作为背景或其他的结果),那么你一定认为这个论点在某个地方出了问题。
一些情境主义者将情境的重要性与Mike的观点结合起来:情境决定哪些可能性需要被排除,哪些不需要。我倾向于同意这一点,但我认为,要支持这一点,需要我们说一些有趣而重要的事情,关于知识是什么以及它是如何工作的。如果我们能做到这一点,那么休谟的论证是可以回答的。

MIke's picture

MIke

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

So I am not sympathetic to replies of the form

So I am not sympathetic to replies of the form "The skeptical argument assumes we know . . ."
Thanks John,
I'm very curious about this. In general, skeptical argument assert that "it is possible that (i) an evil demon is decieving you about x, or (ii) an evil scientist has you attached to a device that causes you to believe x, or..... That is, it seems plain that skeptical arguments assume some modal knowledge--some knowledge of what is possible.
现在假设没有人提出怀疑的论点,声称我可能在任何方面被欺骗/误导。假设他们甚至不声称拥有那么多模态知识。怀疑论的论点如何才能不因此失去影响力?如果怀疑论者不知道我有可能被一个疯狂的科学家所欺骗,等等,那么就没有多少知识主体需要关心的。简而言之,为什么代理必须排除已知不可能的替代方案?我看不出他们有什么理由这么做。这就是为什么我极力主张,那些怀疑论者必须声称,他们至少知道,这种替代方案是可能的。此外,这就是为什么我认为休谟(就我所知)不能确切地说我们是如何知道这一点的。

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Mike, What makes the arguments interesting, on

Mike,
What makes the arguments interesting, on my view, is not that there is someone who is willing to defend them, and therefore someone who is committed to both the premises and conclusion. What makes them interesting, rather, is that the premises looks good to us, but we want to avoid the conclusion. This is a theoretical problem, not a practical or rhetorical problem, such as asserting something while at the same time denying the sort of knoweldge implied by the assertion.
Look at it this way-- the skeptical arguments would be interesting even if there were no one willing to assert them. We non-skeptics would still have exactly the same problem, i.e. that all the premises seem right whereas the conclusion seems wrong. We still want to know which premise to deny and why.

aaron's picture

aaron

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

John, My belief is that the ultimate skeptical

John,
我认为,最终的怀疑论立场是无用的,因为它会转移任何有意义的哲学辩论。我完全同意我们的知识是有限的——我们不确定我们是否只存在于一个宇宙中,或者我们在另一个维度中没有第三只手,或者我们星系外的卫星是否真的是由绿色的奶酪做成的。但要进行有意义的哲学辩论,必须有一些共同点,有一些开始的地方。我们必须在问题的边界上达成一致,这就需要做出假设。
Consider the woodpecker vs. goldfinch argument - one could argue they are different by pointing out the structure of the bones, provide DNA analysis, and any other number of scientific means of conclusively proving they are not the same. But then the skeptic says:
1) Your instruments might be faulty. All of them.
2) How do we know that the DNA for every woodpecker is different from the DNA of every goldfinch without testing them all?
3) Your samples are tainted with human DNA, due to handling...
Yes, those are all possibilities, but there is simply no end to them. There has to be a reachable probability, a place where we can say, "Based on this, I'm quite positive a goldfinch and a woodpecker are not the same." The true skeptic will never let you get there - if all else fails, he will whip out "reality isn't what it appears to be", and then you can't win no matter what you say.
在某种程度上,要想论证任何问题,就必须假设一些事实。问现实的本质是一个独立的问题,它胜过所有其他的问题。这是休谟论证的致命缺陷——这是一个好问题,但不是一个可以挑战其他一切的好问题。为了继续通过怀疑论论证,我们需要理解现实的真正本质。但如果我们知道,怀疑者会问:“你真的理解现实的本质吗?”你怎么知道的?这是唯一的现实吗?”然后我们再一次面对语义论证,如果我们有一个,我们在语言上总是可以有两个。

MIke's picture

MIke

Tuesday, March 27, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

约翰,我想我看到了。I was wondering how som

John,
I think I see it. I was wondering how someone (say, the skeptic, you or I) could reach the skeptical conclusion without assuming some modal knowledge. It does not seem possible. I guess we agree about that, right? Now two cases. Suppose I'm considering Unger's argument and so assuming Unger's epistemological standard's. If Unger is right, then I know that it is possible that all of my experience is being manipulated only if I am certain that it is possible that all of my experience is being manipulated, right? For Unger (I mean, the Unger of Ignorance) I know p iff. I am certain that p. Suppose that's right. In that case, I would know it's possible that p iff. I am certain that it is possible that p. But when it comes to such modal claims, there is not so much that I'm certain about. If certainty is required for knowledge, then I don't know that it is possible that all of my experience is being manipulated. The second case applies the same reasoning to Hume. So all I'm really suggesting is that we apply the epistemic standards that the skeptic insists on (whether or not I or you happen to find them reasonable)to the formulation of the skeptical challenge. The skeptical standards are right only if we don't know that there is skeptical challenge. It's basically an argument from self-defeat. Not persuasive?

Guest's picture

Guest

Wednesday, March 28, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Does anyone have any philosophical sources that di

有没有人有讨论(明显的)第一原则的哲学来源(即“一个人在证据E的基础上知道p,只有当E排除了p的其他可能性”)?Cheers

Guest's picture

Guest

Wednesday, March 28, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Aaron, You are imagining a debate with a commit

Aaron,
You are imagining a debate with a committed skeptic, and you realize that such a person can always raise questions about any claim that is made by his opponent in the debate. You also realize that such a conversation could get nowhere, so long as the skeptic remains consistent in his/her refusal to allow any claim. I entirely agree. If you ever meet such a person, by all means don't get into a conversation with him. But the skeptical arguments I am interested in don't ask questions, and nowhere do they depend on an assumption to the effect that no claims are admissable. So I don't see how your points address those arguments.

Guest's picture

Guest

Wednesday, March 28, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Jeremy, I recommend the following: DeRose, K

Jeremy,
I recommend the following:
DeRose, K. and T. Warfield. Eds. (1999), Skepticism: A Contemporary Reader. New York: Oxford University Press. See especially DeRose's Introduction.
Pritchard, D. (2002a), ?Recent Work on Radical Skepticism.? American Philosophical Quarterly, vol. 39. no. 3, pp. 215-257.

Guest's picture

Guest

Wednesday, March 28, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Mike, I don't find arguments from self-defeat p

Mike,
I don't find arguments from self-defeat persuasive here, partly for the reasons I have already given. But here is a different point: even if such arguments show that skeptical arguments are mistaken, they don?t show where they are mistaken. That is, they don?t show which assumptions of the arguments are false, and so no lesson is learned from them. Here is another thought: I am already assuming that the skeptical argument is mistaken somewhere. I think I know that I know that here is a hand, and so I don?t need self-defeat arguments to show me or convince me that the skeptical arguments go wrong. The interesting question is WHERE do they go wrong.
I think we can distinguish three grades of success in a response to a skeptical argument, each being more satisfying than the former: a) identify an assumption that we need not accept, b) find a reason for thinking that some assumption is false, and c) find an explanation for why some assumption is false, e.g. come up with a theory of knowledge that explains the mistake. Notice that an objection from self-defeat does not even give us the least satisfying of these grades.

aaron's picture

aaron

Thursday, March 29, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

John, I am directly addressing the second step

John,
I am directly addressing the second step of the skeptical argument, which you listed thusly:
"The second step in the skeptical argument is to point out that there are various possibilities that are inconsistent with what we claim to know about the external world. For example, it is possible that things appear to me visually just as they do now, but that I am actually lying in my bed asleep rather than sitting at my desk awake. It is possible that things appear to Descartes?s just as they do, but that he is actually the victim of an evil demon, a disembodied spirit who only dreams that he inhabits a material world and is presently seated by the fire. To be clear, it is no part of the skeptical argument that such alternative possibilities are true, or even that they are somewhat likely. The point is only that they are possibilities, and so undermine our knowledge if our evidence does not rule them out."
My point is simply that is impossible to rule out evil demons and such. It is the same as trying to prove a negative - proving that God does not exist, for example. The second step of the skeptical argument would clearly qualify as forcing us to prove a negative, would it not?

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, April 1, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Aaron, But this sounds like you are simply agre

Aaron,
But this sounds like you are simply agreeing with the skeptic-- i.e. that there are various possbilities and they can't be ruled out. Maybe you are saying that they don't need to be ruled out for us to have knowledge.
On my view we have to get clear about what we mean by "rule out." On some readings, I think we can rule out the dream possibility, and so the premise is false. On other readings, I think it turns out false that we need to rule out all the alternative possibilities. But either way, there is something in the argument to deny, and progress to be made by explaining why we can challenge the argument at that point.

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, April 3, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Hello there, Interesting discussion. I want to

Hello there,
有趣的讨论。我想提出一个建议,也许能更好地表达像肯·泰勒和其他提出类似观点的人的担忧。
As well as justification of beliefs, we might perhaps define another quality: blameworthiness for believing something. (Just bear with me and it will make more sense at the end.)
Despite the moral connotations, the notion of blameworthiness I have here has nothing to do with blameworthiness in that sense. It's "epistemic blameworthiness" if I may so fancy. Suppose that a chess player, without due reflection and calculation, decides upon a move M. The chess player can be "blamed" for his belief that M should be his next move, since he decided upon it without any reflection.
Now suppose that one day you wake up and see a powerful demon who is laughing at all the foolish beliefs you just had and chastising you for not taking skepticism seriously. "But," you say, "there was no EVIDENCE whatsoever for believing in a skeptical hypothesis. True, I may not have had the correct beliefs. Nonetheless, given the evidence I had, these were the BEST beliefs that I could possibly have. Surely, I can't be BLAMED for having them." And this time, you wake up to find yourself in the Matrix.
My point is that even if the skeptic's arguments work for justification and knowledge, there is a sense of blameworthiness for believing that is substantially weaker than both justification and knowledge and for which the skeptics arguments don't work.

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, April 3, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

只是一个附录。Here is the distinction betwe

只是一个附录。
Here is the distinction between justification and epistemic blameworthiness:
A weak chess player might contemplate over a chess position and after due reflection may decide on a move. The move may be indeed bad and in the light of proper analysis, completely UNJUSTIFIED. Nevertheless, the weak chess player can't be blamed for deciding on that, since he did his "epistemic duty".
I have a feeling that this discussion is likely to spill into the discussion concerning ethics of belief.

Guest's picture

Guest

Saturday, April 21, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

To strive above all at holding as many true and as

To strive above all at holding as many true and as few false beliefs as possible, is not rational. This is one of the valuable points made by Mikael Stenmark in a discussion with Vincent Brümmer about the theism-atheism debate.
Brümmer他自己经常争论说,既然人类不仅仅是知道的主体,而是行动者,他们的决定的合理性,关于采取哪一种生活的观点,不能充分地从一个纯粹的认识论的观点,但应该考虑到实用主义的考虑。在展开他的论点时,他借鉴了马丁·海德格尔(Martin Heidegger)的著作,但类似的见解也可能来自路德维希·维特根斯坦(Ludwig Wittgenstein)。
事实上,我认为休谟——不像笛卡尔——在发展他的怀疑论时,以他自己的方式,试图精确地阐明这一点。他并不是要说服任何人相信怀疑论,而是要说明某种认识论方法的荒谬。明智的做法,理性的方法,是以一种适合自己的方式生活下去。
当代一位重要的思想家广泛地发展了这种理性方法,他就是温泽尔·范·胡斯汀。他从进化的角度看待理性,这有助于他将理性视为一种适应能力,一种为了有意义地生活而使用的能力。这与科学哲学中关注工具价值科学理论的观点相联系,即它们旨在解释,预测和控制。
From this kind of perspective the crucial question as far as our basic assumptions about the world is concerned, is not whether we can prove them, but rather whether it is wise to live with them, whether they help us to live well. And perhaps behind it all lies the intuition that if something works, that must be because it has some link with how things really are. And with the question: What does it mean for something to be "real"?
- Gerrit Brand
(Visit my blog at gerritbrand.blogspot.com)

Guest's picture

Guest

Tuesday, April 24, 2007 -- 5:00 PM

Hello! I hope no one minds me giving some opinion

Hello!
我希望没有人介意我对这篇文章发表一些看法。
I haven't read through every post above, but I would like to challenge this proposition.
1. A person knows that p on the basis of evidence E, only if E rules out alternative possibilities to p.
This seems ambiguous to me. Intuitively I should have thought if you recognise something, you recognise that thing. If your recognising that thing e.g. your wife consisted in ruling out other possibilities, that would seem highly implausible. How do you know which other possibilities are the ones you need to rule out? And why just these possibilities? On the other hand if you recognise your wife directly, then this as a matter of logic automatically does rule out all other possibilities because they are not your wife. So does this proposition 1) mean a) in order to recognise something (or have a reason for supposing something) this must entail some other possibilities are ruled out, or does it mean b) the nature of having evidence for E consists in ruling out other possibilities?
即使是a)也可能会受到挑战。例如,有人可能会说,如果你一生中唯一看到的是一种红色,那么这种知觉体验就永远不会在你的意识中记录下来。我们必须至少有另一种视觉体验,这样我们才能将一件事与另一件事进行对比,从而记住其中任何一件事。这是a)的一个论点,似乎是可信的。但假设你只经历了一次你一生中最剧烈的痛苦,这是否意味着你永远不会意识到哪里出了问题?你将如何,或者你能如何着手解决在争论中看似合理的问题?
Justin

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, March 15, 2009 -- 5:00 PM

An Equation of Truth Truth is when the subjecti

An Equation of Truth
Truth is when the subjective = the objective
Or simply: Subject = Object
Or more simply: =
=就是真理。
其他的一切充其量只是可能的或不确定的。
Life without measure is equal and equal makes the Universe One.
Equal = "free at last, free at last, free at last..."
"The truth shall set us free."
=
MJA

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, May 10, 2009 -- 5:00 PM

The old bottom line: Apply the skeptical argume

The old bottom line: Apply the skeptical argument to itself --- things could be another way entirely,we're brains in vats and so on ----and you will be skeptical of skepticism; things could be other than the way skeptics depict them. Skeptics, since they maintain that they know they are correct,cannot admit that things could be other than they say--without contradiction. If the reply is that one cannot apply skeptical argument to itself---why not?
奇怪的是,要使怀疑论的论点成立,怀疑论必须坚持,似乎世界是一种特殊的方式,而不是其他方式——否则怀疑论就不能认为我们不能知道事物的真实状态。那么问题来了,怀疑论是如何知道事物存在真实状态的。他们从哪里得到的?

Guest's picture

Guest

Sunday, May 10, 2009 -- 5:00 PM

If we'll never know if we know--have the correct

If we'll never know if we know--have the correct thought of-- the true state of things, then I could be wrong in holding that I don't
know the true state of things. But this seems intuitively impossible---how can I not know what thought
arises within me?